Friday, 6 March 2009

The Charlton Heston Question

Some ideas in my head, wanted to get them somewhere safer (more permanent?) than the flow and flux of my (unreliable) mental equipment, so here we go.

I’ve been thinking on the question of the neutrality of technology, which is a question I think needs to come near the top of my thesis argument. Can we ask questions as to the inherent morality of given technologies, disregarding particular instances of their use? Thus, the title of this posting comes in a fashion after McLuhan, who responds to the suggestion that individual modern technologies are neither good nor bad: “That is the voice of the current somnambulism. Suppose we were to say ... “Firearms are in themselves neither good nor bad; it is the way they are used that determines their value.” That is, if the slugs reach the right people firearms are good.” (McLuhan, Understanding Media, 11)

I’ve been thinking through this example, still used by the National Rifle Association in the US to counter those who seek to limit the availability of guns to civilians in the form of “guns don’t kill people, people do” (hence “the Charlton Heston Question, “ in honour/parody of the late president/spokesman of the NRA). I think it is nonsense to talk only of the particular uses of technologies and disregard the inherent ways in which they work on and shape the ways we relate to the world, our very psycho-social fabric. The very fact that we create guns at all, regardless of their eventual use, is, I think, instructive as to human nature.

For McLuhan, of course, mediating technologies are never neutral, they implicitly shape the messages they carry, in much the way a given metaphor transforms (and thus biases) our understanding of a concept – example: “all the world’s a stage and all the men and women merely players”, which might tend to make us see ourselves as actors spouting words karaoke style from a predetermined script, but neglects to tell us, then, who the writer, the director, the audience, even the lighting-guy, is (presumably they’re all God, but then this means that this metaphor is implicitly shaping our view of the world as one created by a creator, who wants to watch over us, who approves or not, etc.) – thus we see the world in a novel way, a little differently, see common objects from new aspects, and hence we come to understand it a little better. Ok, so this is a good thing BUT we must heed the baggage and biases, and so iterate the ways in which that media (or metaphor) implicitly shapes the way in which we see the world.

Which is a somewhat similar starting point (though they reach different conclusions) to Heidegger, whose “The Question Concerning Technology,” (In: "Basic Writings", London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, pp.287-317) seeks to address the essence of technology in relation to human existence. There, he posits the view of technology as neutral to be the instrumental/anthropological definition. Thus “According to ancient doctrine”, he advises, “the essence of a thing is considered to be what the things is” (288) and through this definition, we arrive at two statements: “One says: Technology is a means to an end. The other says: Technology is a human activity” (288). In these terms, technology is neutered, reduced to nothing more than a human activity pursuant to particular ends.

For Heidegger, this “uncannily correct” (288) definition does not, of course, tell the whole story. For him, in the terms of his earlier work, this would be the ontic explanation, correctly identifying states of affairs but not telling us what it is to be in this relationship. We have privileged ourselves, as the efficient cause of the coming to be of technology, at the neglect of Aristotle’s other three causes: material, formal, final. The material a technology is made of, the particular form it takes, and its telos, that which gives it its cultural bounds as a technology for a purpose, are all responsible for, all at play in the “bringing-forth” of, a given technology.  

Thus the potentialities of the stuff and structure of given materials, along with (and most importantly for Heidegger) the cultural context into which that technology is to be employed, are all necessary causes alongside that of the efficient cause. Given this, in the example of the coming to be of a sacrificial chalice, the silversmith is the efficient cause, “not at all because he, in working, brings about the finished sacrificial chalice as if it were the effect of a making ... The silversmith considers carefully and gathers together the three aforementioned ways of being responsible and indebted. To consider carefully is in Greek legein, logos. Legein is rooted in apophainesthai, to bring forward into appearance. The silversmith is co-responsible as that from whence the sacred vessel’s bringing-forth and subsistence take and retain their departure.” (291, author’s italics)

So technology is an occasion of “revealing” rather than creation, bring out of concealment into unconcealment, and this, if right has big implications for our understanding of what it is to be the cause of something, as inventor, creator or author. If we aren’t in full control of the coming to be of technology, then the instrumental/anthropological definition is deficient because it neglects the ways in which our technologies act on us, the way we are influenced to bring them to be. Heidegger goes on to argue that our true relation to technology is one of the enframing (Gestell) of nature, challenging it as a “standing-reserve” of resources to be plundered, and that this has a negative impact on our existence. I don’t want to tackle that can of worms just now though, rather just use the first part of his argument (can I just use the first part without being bound to accept the latter? – I think so, but maybe not) as an illustration of why the view of technologies as neutral is deficient, to demonstrate that human intention is not the sole author of technology, and to iterate the reasons why we must attend to the ways in which they are working on us as well as us on them.  

For Langdon Winner, in “The Whale and the Reactor: A Search for Limits in an Age of High Technology,” technologies have political consequences:

“The things we call “technologies” are ways of building order in our world. Many technical devices and systems important in everyday life contain possibilities for many different ways of ordering human activity. Consciously or unconsciously, deliberately or inadvertently, societies choose structures for technologies that influence how people are going to work, communicate, travel, consume, and so forth over a very long time. In the processes by which structuring decisions are made, different people are situated differently and possess unequal degrees of power as well as unequal levels of awareness.” (28-9)

Thus, he proposes that the neutral view of technology blinds us to an essential matter of enquiry: “we usually do not stop to inquire whether a given device might have been designed and built in such a way that it produces a set of consequences logically and temporally prior to any of its professed uses.... If our moral and political language for evaluating technology includes only categories having to do with tools and uses, if it does not include attention to the meaning of the designs and arrangements of our artifacts, then we will be blinded to much that is intellectually and practically crucial.” (25)

All of which (I think) I agree with, and leads back into my research, where the definition of materiality I gave in my last post (“materiality: the effects and affects of carrier on experience of content”) can be, perhaps, be sharpened into the research question:

“What are the material differences between analogue and digital forms, and in what logically and temporally prior ways do these differences hold the potential to effect and affect creation, consumption, and curation of content?”

As an example of the sorts of questions this is trying to pose: what does it mean that I can put a hyperlink here to something which may or may not be related to this piece, how does that effect my writing this, your (if you’re there) reading of it (did you immediately link through to it, or if you didn’t, will you ignore it now that I’ve made it questionable whether its even connected, will you even come back to read the rest of this if you do click on it?), and the effects on the archive (e.g. if this blog were being archived, would that page now be considered part of this work?). How does this sort of interlinking of information affect us? Is there anything in the truisms that concentration suffers, depth of thought sacrificed for a life of surfing/scratching the surface? Are we all living essentially post-modern lives on the net, lives of a random flow of unrelated shreds of information, a loss of traditional narrative form for one where any casual interconnection is taken to be symbolic of the larger web of meaning(lessness)? Etc, etc, etc. Wild speculation at the end, I know, but that’s where all this stuff is eventually heading ...

 

3 comments:

  1. Neutral in what sense? Technology is designed to be used in a certain way, and shapes the user in a certain way. The intended use of the technology is a separate thing to the intent behind creating it and to the intent with which the user utilizes it. The way in which society represents a technology may also present a different sense in which the technology may or may not be 'neutral.' We must also ask, Neutral in reference to what? Heston would have argued that the rifle (if he had enough of a mind, and if we pried from his 'cold dead hands') was neutral in the sense that it had no intentionality in and of itself. He would have been wrong, of course, in the sense that it is designed to kill things, and thus is by no means neutral (just ask the Buddhist priest, who does not kill anything if he can help it).

    As to the difference between technology 'as a human thing' and 'as a means to an end' ... I'm afraid that I don't understand what is meant. The 'end' in question is human, certainly, so 'means to an end' does not exclude that thing being human. Where you might make some headway is in thinking that technology is about 'techne', so must involve some aspect of craft or art, not necessarily some functional component as such. Thus, 'a means to an end' may be said to entail 'human' but not vice versa. Even so, I do not understand how technology is neutered, nor what is meant by the term; if it is to say that technology is rendered neutral, a-moral in the true sense, then I think that the argument doesn't really get anywhere.

    You might consider the origins to the word 'genius' in your consideration of the nature of creation. OED says, "With reference to classical pagan belief: The tutelary god or attendant spirit allotted to every person at his birth, to govern his fortunes and determine his character, and finally to conduct him out of the world; also, the tutelary and controlling spirit similarly connected with a place, an institution, etc." So, genius - to which we may attribute acts of creation - was regarded as being outside of the human being. This is interesting, because it absolves the human of responsibility both for anything great and anything horrible. The Genius is also known as the Muse, I believe.

    In any event, enjoying this stuff. Hope you'll write more!

    ReplyDelete
  2. Hi dave, I maybe wasn’t clear: the question of neutrality is the one I was posing when I asked: “Can we ask questions as to the inherent morality of given technologies, disregarding particular instances of their use?” Thus, yes, the intentionality lying behind construction, and eventual uses made of, a particular technology (say blog software) are really important to examine, but what I was trying to get at, is: “In what ways do particular technologies influence (construct) being?” I.e., how do our technologies shape the uses we make of them, and what does this tell us about the way our modes of reflection/ communication/ memorialisation are structured. Your point about Heston’s rifle is exactly what I was getting at; people do argue that technologies are merely passive instruments for the intentional use of humans, and disregard the fact that particular technologies a priori shape the particular ways they will be used, that they make certain ways of being easier or more difficult, and thus influence being itself. It’s this attitude I was seeking to address, because it comes into play in justifying what I think is now going to be the strategy of my thesis, to start first with an examination of the composite stuff and structure of the phenomena (letters/diaries and blogs/social networking systems), before then going on to examine the particular uses made of them in the light of this.

    As to your second point, on the difference between tech as a “human thing” and as a “means to an end,” my first instinct would be to advise reading Heidegger, I probably just botch it, but here goes: These are the two (ontic) definitions of technology that he finds produced by the “doctrine” of thought which considers technologies as objects (in the Cartesian sense), rather than examining them ontologically as tools we use in the course of our being-in-the-world (i.e., in their ready-to-hand mode). We make tools, systems, etc., in the course of our human activity, and we do so in the pursuit of certain ends (I make a shelter because I want to stay warm/dry). At the end of the paragraph I conflate the two (the sentence “technology is neutered, reduced to nothing more than a human activity pursuant to particular ends”) for the sake of brevity - Heidegger might not do this. The crucial point is though, that Heidegger wants us to see that we are not masters of our “creations,” that we are brought to “create” them, and that as they are parts of our being-in-the-world that they are part of the structure our being. The use of the word “neutered” is in relation to Heidegger’s argument that if we accept the purely ontic explanation, then yes, we will see technology as amoral. BUT, this isn’t the point of the argument, this is laying the foundations for his showing us that ontologically this ISN’T the case, that indeed we are shaped by our technologies (because of an attitude of “enframing” which sets us in opposition to nature) and thus it does get to the root of the problem I posed at the start of the piece: are technologies neutral?

    Your point on techne is a little unclear, I’m aware of the definition of techne, but can’t fit in exactly how thinking in terms of craft/art specifically changes things - can you explain?

    With regard to creation and the etymology of the word “genius,” that’s really interesting but I don’t think the introduction of etymology or metaphysics ever really helps clarify things. The ancients might’ve attributed genius to higher powers, but what does that change about things these days?

    Anyways, thanks for the comments/ questions – tis good to keep some dialogue going!

    ReplyDelete
  3. UPDATE: I've just read this by Michael Heim, which I think sums up what both Heidegger and McLuhan are trying to get at better than I've done:

    “Both Heidegger and McLuhan felt an inner relationship to their epoch. Each believed that he was interpreting a destiny that the next generation would receive, and each believed that the legacy of his reflections on technology was far more important than his own personal value judgements about technology.... Both Heidegger and McLuhan saw intimate connections between information technology and the way the mind works.... What synchronized their visions is the crucial role that technology plays in defining reality, in operating as an invisible backdrop within which the content or entities of the world appear.”

    This is from pages 543-4 of: Heim, Michael H., 1997, “Heidegger and McLuhan and the Essence of Virtual Reality”. In: Scharff, Robert C. and Dusek, Val (Eds.), 2003, Philosophy of Technology: The Technological Condition – An Anthology, Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 539-55, (Originally published in: Heim, Michael H., The Metaphysics of Virtual Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 55-72).

    ReplyDelete